If one prizes moderation and self-control, and seeks to manifest these traits, then one is honoring Sophrosyne (sophrosune), the Greek goddess exemplifying these qualities. She is the daimona, or personified spirit, who is best represented as temperance, that is, the sort of self-restraint and self-control that derive from self-knowledge. If one follows the Delphic Oracle's command to "know thyself," and therefore one is aware of one's limitations, and most importantly one is aware of what one does not know, then the spirit of Sophrosyne is evoked. Sophrosyne is the subject matter of Plato's dialogue Charmides, wherein is discussed self-knowledge, and the wisdom and moral health that are attainable through rational understanding of oneself, and particularly of understanding oneself as a being with limitations. The dialogue does not achieve any strong resolution on the question of sophrosyne. What the dialogue does reveal is that sophrosyne is a virtue, and as such represents a state that people of excellence recognize and honor, for it is an aristocratic virtue, one that represents self-command through self-knowledge, and through sophrosyne we achieve the a level of dignity appropriate for a human being of excellent character. An inseparable part of this self-knowledge is knowledge of what we owe to others, according to the nature of our relations to particular others. If we possess the requisite self-knowledge, then we are able to 'mind our own business' in relation to others, for self-knowledge informs us of the worth and the significance of our experiences, of our social standing, and of what and what are not appropriate ambitions for ourselves, as established by our abilities and our limitations.
The concept of sophrosyne was central to the thinking of Aesara of Lucania, a woman philosopher of ancient times who, similar to Socrates, saw the soul as tripartite, consisting of mind (intellect: nous), spirit, and desire. One who pursues sophrosyne seeks to understand the nature of, and cultivate a balance amongst, these three (often) competing aspects of the human condition. If one is capable of grasping sufficiently these constituents of human nature, and one works to bring them into balance, that is, one endeavors to not allow one aspect to exceed its just proportion and thus dominate the others, thereby disordering the self, then one is able to realize the harmony of soul all reasonable persons seek to establish and to enjoy.
0 Comments
It is not true that in order to do good, we must know the good thing to do. We can, after all, do good by accident. Perhaps, for example, in driving down the street we accidently hit and kill a rabid dog that otherwise would have gone on to bite people. Or perhaps our neighbor has performed several favors for us, such as cutting our lawn when we had a broken leg, and we wanted his good deeds to be acknowledged so we nominated him for a good neighbor award or the like, which involved publication of his picture, and it turned out that someone recognized him as a serial rapist that had terrorized a nearby community, and subsequently he was arrested, prosecuted, and jailed for years, saving many woman from a horrible assault. Even more extreme, we might do good when our intent was to do evil. Perhaps I wanted to harm a neighbor and I poisoned his drinking water well, with the intent of great harm, but as it turns out, the poison I poured into his well was the precise mixture to counteract poison someone else had just poured into the well, and the water was safe to drink.
These examples reveal that doing good need not always involve virtue on our part. Virtue requires knowing the right thing to do in a given circumstance, and then doing that thing. Now it is certainly true that in endeavoring to do good we in fact cause harm, but so long as our intent was honorable, and so long as we had undertaken prior to acting all that would be expected of a reasonable person in respect to understanding the situation and what the proper course of action should be, then most often we are held blameless if our act does cause unintended harm. Essential for our acting virtuously is what the ancient Greeks understood as phronesis, which can be defined as practical wisdom. Aristotle placed particular importance on this trait, for without wisdom on what is the right thing to be done in a given situation, we can hardly put our other virtues to good use. Aristotle understood phronesis as a skill we develop through practice, through reflecting on our acts and seeking to thereby gain wisdom on how we might improve on our future actions. Hence, if we possess phronesis, then we know how to act - appropriately - in a given situation. The act itself is identified as praxis, which signifies the actual process of performing what phronesis informs us is the right thing to do in the particular situation. To improve, therefore, our ability to act appropriately in the world, we must do all we can to gain in practical wisdom, we need, that is, to maximize our phronesis. As the saying goes, much is lost in translation, and the truth of this statement often is in evidence when we make use of words originating in ancient Greece, perhaps the most prominent example of this loss or distortion is found in the term eudaimonia. The term, if not precisely ubiquitous. is commonly enough encountered that many believe that they can define the word, and do so as 'happiness'. While not an incorrect definition, it certainly is an inadequate one, for the term, to the ancient Greeks, encompasses far more than mere happiness. The true translation of the term is "having a good indwelling spirt or daemon." But what does this mean, precisely?
Perhaps the best we can do today to recapture what the ancient Greeks understood as being represented in the use of the term is the concept of 'human flourishing'. Aristotle believed that the way to flourishing was through arete, which essentially is understood as virtue or excellence, with excellence being understood as the fullest realization of something's or someone's inherent function. For Aristotle, the arete of a knife, for example, is realized when the knife fulfills its intended function, and cuts well. An eye achieves arete if it performs well its function of vision. Thus the virtue of an eye is present to the extent that the eye performs its inherent function of seeing. A human being, per Aristotle (amongst others), achieves arete if that individual is able to perform well his or her various functions, such as courage and intelligence, thereby realizing his or her fullest potential. Given the nature of a human being, as Aristotle understood this nature, that is, given that the capacity for reason is greatest in a human being beyond all other creatures, then the arete of a human being consists of a life dedicated to contemplation, of thinking about thinking, and the wisdom that results from this life of contemplation. Eudaimonia, then, is far more than is represented in the modern usage of the term happiness, and is perhaps best understood as the concept of 'human flourishing', with this flourishing of course involving human happiness, but substantially more. We, as human beings, achieve eudaimonia through virtue or excellence in all we do, and we endeavor to develop fully our capacity for courage, for reason, for living well through contemplation of the good life for ourselves and for others. If we do so, if we value arete and strive for its realization, then we achieve well-being, and we can be said to possess a good indwelling spirit. We then experience the blessed state of eudaimonia. Anthropologists in their research into human behavior throughout cultures across all of known human history have revealed the rather dispiriting truth that there is little we can conceive of regarding that behavior, no matter how heinous we might judge the act or the practice, that was not at some time and in some place, sanctioned. Many people today, unwilling to or incapable of embracing a particular worldview and ethical standard such as promulgated by a specific religion, accept the Shakespearean perspective that "there is nothing either good or bad, but thinking makes it so," as articulated by Hamlet. Such persons accept, whether they might express their viewpoint this way precisely or not, a relativist metaphysics that allows no room for universal moral standards.
|
AuthorUndergraduate and graduate degrees in philosophy, both with highest honors. Archives
May 2023
Categories |
Site powered by Weebly. Managed by Bluehost